克鲁斯卡尔树定理
TREE函数、Kruskal树定理(英语:Kruskal's tree theorem)是逆数学的突出示例。由安德鲁·瓦兹尼推测并由Joseph Kruskal (1960)证明。
In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
History
The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved within ATR0 (a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion), and a finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function.
Statement
The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write T1 ≤ T2 if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that
- For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of F(v),
- If w is any successor of v in T1, then F(w) is a successor of F(v), and
- If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from F(w1) to F(w2) in T2 contains F(v).
If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some i < j so that Ti ≤ Tj.)
Weak tree function
Define tree(n), the weak tree function, as the length of the longest sequence of 1-labelled trees (i.e. X = {1}) such that:
- The tree at position k in the sequence has no more than k + n vertices, for all k.
- No tree is homeomorphically embeddable into any tree following it in the sequence.
It is known that tree(1) = 2, tree(2) = 5, and tree(3) ≥ 844424930131960,[1][需要较佳来源] but TREE(3) (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
Friedman's work
For a countable label set , Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like 古德斯坦定理 or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where has order one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in <span class="ilh-all " data-orig-title="ATR0" data-lang-code="en" data-lang-name="英语" data-foreign-title="arithmetical transfinite recursion">[[:ATR0|ATR0]] ,[2] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[3] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[4] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[5][6] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
1-CA0.
Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[来源请求]
TREE(3)
Suppose that P(n) is the statement:
- There is some m such that if T1,...,Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Tk has n+k vertices, then Ti ≤ Tj for some i < j.
All the statements P(n) are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and 柯尼格引理. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that P(n) is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "P(n) is true for all n".[7] Moreover the length of the shortest proof of P(n) in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the 阿克曼函数 for example. The least m for which P(n) holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take TREE(n)[*] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
- There is a sequence T1,...,Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that Ti ≤ Tj does not hold for any i < j ≤ m.
The TREE sequence begins TREE(1) = 1, TREE(2) = 3, then suddenly TREE(3) explodes to a value so immensely large that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's n(4),[**] are extremely small by comparison. In fact, it is much larger than nn(5)(5). A lower bound for n(4), and hence an extremely weak lower bound for TREE(3), is AA(187196)(1),[9] where A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)). 葛立恒数, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound AA(187196)(1). It can be shown that the growth-rate of the function TREE is at least in the fast-growing hierarchy. AA(187196)(1) is approximately , where gx is Graham's function.
参见
- Paris–Harrington theorem
- Kanamori–McAloon theorem
- Robertson–Seymour theorem
注释
- ^ * Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
- ^ ** n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10] .
Category:Trees (graph theory)
参考
- Citations
- ^ TREE sequence. Googology Wiki | Fandom. [9 July 2020]. (原始内容存档于2020-01-09).
- ^ Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
- ^ Friedman 2002, p. 60
- ^ Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
- ^ Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
- ^ Marcone 2001, p. 8–9
- ^ Smith 1985, p. 120
- ^ Friedman, Harvey. 273:Sigma01/optimal/size. Ohio State University Department of Maths. 28 March 2006 [8 August 2017]. (原始内容存档于2022-12-07).
- ^ Friedman, Harvey M. Enormous Integers In Real Life (PDF). Ohio State University. 1 June 2000 [8 August 2017]. (原始内容存档 (PDF)于2016-10-18).
- ^ Friedman, Harvey M. Long Finite Sequences (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics: 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). 8 October 1998 [8 August 2017]. (原始内容存档 (PDF)于2017-08-09).
- Bibliography
- Friedman, Harvey M., Internal finite tree embeddings. Reflections on the foundations of mathematics (Stanford, CA, 1998), Lect. Notes Log. 15, Urbana, IL: Assoc. Symbol. Logic: 60–91, 2002, MR 1943303
- Gallier, Jean H., What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory (PDF), Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 1991, 53 (3): 199–260 [2022-11-07], MR 1129778, doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E , (原始内容存档 (PDF)于2023-02-03)
- Kruskal, J. B., Well-quasi-ordering, the tree theorem, and Vazsonyi's conjecture (PDF), Transactions of the American Mathematical Society (American Mathematical Society), May 1960, 95 (2): 210–225 [2022-11-07], JSTOR 1993287, MR 0111704, doi:10.2307/1993287, (原始内容存档 (PDF)于2021-10-21)
- Marcone, Alberto. Wqo and bqo theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. 2001, 21: 303–330 [2022-11-07]. (原始内容存档 (PDF)于2022-05-08).
- Nash-Williams, C. St.J. A., On well-quasi-ordering finite trees, Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc., 1963, 59 (4): 833–835, Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N, MR 0153601, S2CID 251095188 请检查
|s2cid=
的值 (帮助), doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844 - Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas. Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 1993, 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-g .
- Simpson, Stephen G., Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees, Harrington, L. A.; Morley, M.; Scedrov, A.; et al (编), Harvey Friedman's Research on the Foundations of Mathematics, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North-Holland: 87–117, 1985
- Smith, Rick L., The consistency strengths of some finite forms of the Higman and Kruskal theorems, Harrington, L. A.; Morley, M.; Scedrov, A.; et al (编), Harvey Friedman's Research on the Foundations of Mathematics, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North-Holland: 119–136, 1985